Expert Intuition VI

Welcome! You are encouraged to register with the site and login (for free). When you register, you support the site and your question history is saved.

     In the realm of the psychology of decision-making, the role of expert intuition is under attack. People's inclination is to trust intuition and to point to many examples, across various disciplines, in which experts are able to make difficult judgments in seemingly negligible amounts of time. But this trust of intuition has been undermined by the research of other psychologists who have taken care to expose and document thoroughly the cognitive biases that can impede both our use of intuition and our ability to judge the use of intuition in a broader sense. How, then, can we know when expert intuition is to be trusted?
     Gary Klein's research has provided a basis on which to establish how expert intuition, also known as naturalistic decision making, works at its best, which it does according to a recognition-primed decision model. One of his studies examined the thought process of experienced fireground commanders, the leaders of firefighter teams. One finding was that fireground commanders do not only consider a small number of options in deciding how to approach a firefighting situation; they tend to consider only one option. When presented with a situation, the commander was observed to think of one option spontaneously and then mentally simulate acting on that proposed course of action to see whether it would work. More specifically, Klein formulated the recognition-primed decision model as occurring in two steps. In the first step, a tentative plan comes to the mind of the expert by an automatic function of associative memory; the situation provides one or more clues recognized by the expert. Second, the plan is mentally simulated to see whether it will work.
     When, then, can expert intuition be tested? Klein's model implies that the successful application of expert intuition will be limited to circumstances in which situational clues are reproduced and can be recognized over time. Situational regularity and individual memory are critical components of success. Reliable intuition is primarily--and, arguably, nothing more than--recognition. By this somewhat controversial inference, intuition is essentially memory. Consequently, all cases in which we might anticipate expert intuition to be valid are not equally conquerable by this faculty. Some environments may not be sufficiently regular to be predictable, and, of course, even in regular environments, the presumed expert must draw on a sufficient depth of practice. We can conclude, for example, that if a dedicated stock picker is to make judgments as skilled as those of a dedicated chess player, that person will do so not by relying primarily on intuition. One might note that, with or without intuition, it is incumbent on any true expert to know the limits of his or her knowledge.

The passage provides support for which of the following statements?

Review: Expert Intuition VI


Explanation

This question gives us no details to latch onto, so we can start by evaluating the answer choices against the main point of the passage and see where that get us. (A) touches on which decision-making method is the best, which is off-topic, since our topic is when expert intuition is properly applied or "at its best." Choice (A) is out. Choice (B) is not entirely implausible, since memory is essential to expert intuition. Choice (C) ventures a statement that we have no support for whatsoever, as other techniques haven't been discussed or explicitly ruled out. So we rule out (C). Choice (D) speculates that the act of simulation requires creativity, but this idea is neither stated nor implied. Further, since the associative memory process is based on experience, quite possibly the simulation process is in fact based on experience and not than creativity. So (D) is out. Choice (E) presents a statement that is not only supported, but required, by the passage. We're told that individual memory is one of the two main elements required for expert intuition to work. Since it's one of two required, it's necessary, but not alone sufficient. We look back to (B). Can we find an objective defect? We can imagine a situation in which various experts all have very good individual memories. One expert may have an even better memory, but it may not do him much good, since they are all at such a high level--and the other experts, say, might have a better ability to simulate in their minds, making them better decision-makers. We can see that (B) could be true, but need not be, while (E) must be true, based on the passage.

The correct answer is (E). Passage 21






If you believe you have found an error in this question or explanation, please contact us and include the question title or URL in your message.